Premium
Toward Global Justice through Benefit‐Sharing
Author(s) -
CHENNELLS ROGER
Publication year - 2010
Publication title -
hastings center report
Language(s) - English
Resource type - Journals
SCImago Journal Rank - 0.515
H-Index - 63
eISSN - 1552-146X
pISSN - 0093-0334
DOI - 10.1353/hcr.0.0220
Subject(s) - bioprospecting , convention on biological diversity , political science , legislation , traditional knowledge , negotiation , law and economics , environmental ethics , business , economic justice , public relations , law , sociology , indigenous , ecology , biodiversity , biology , philosophy
Biopiracy" is a critical term coined to describe the practice of "bioprospecting," which falls short of today's ethical and legal standards. While bioprospecting is the age-old search for natural chemical products, biopiracy conjures up lurid images of ruthless perpetrators, ill-gotten riches, and plundered victims. These terms have emerged since the Convention for Biological Diversity was approved in 1994 by 191 countries. The CBD aims to conserve biological diversity, to sustainably use its components, and to equitably share "benefits arising out of the use of genetic resources." Conventions state shared principles but do not themselves provide protection. That depends on legislation enabling the components of a coherent international access and benefit-sharing regime. Right now, only a handful of countries in Africa and Asia are pursuing this kind of legislation. Joseph Millum endeavors in this issue to resolve one of the thorny questions in the negotiation of this regime--namely, "How should the benefits of bioprospecting be shared?" Current good practice holds that benefit-sharing agreements be negotiated with the local community in a process that ensures "prior informed consent," and that benefits be shared in return for access to both genetic resources and use of the community's associated traditional knowledge. Millum focuses on the moral justification for this practice, in light of doubts over communities' formal ownership of organisms and the fact that much traditional knowledge is both in the public domain and the result of past, not current, individual effort. Using idealized cases, he seeks to defend the practice of benefit-sharing from within a Western understanding of property and justice--and in my view, succeeds admirably. After concluding that an indigenous community holds rights in biodiversity as "common" (as opposed to private or collective) property, he ponders who may decide to grant access, for what price, and how and with whom the benefits are to be shared. He notes that the national government "might not represent fully the interests of such communities," which understates the harsh reality that most indigenous peoples are politically powerless. Their interests are seldom served by their states, which under Article 15 of the CBD have sovereign rights over biological resources. Millum also acknowledges that identifying "legitimate decision-makers" in indigenous communities is a practical concern and that indigenous governance is often unclear or in flux. …