z-logo
Premium
One Ought Too Many
Author(s) -
Finlay Stephen,
Snedegar Justin
Publication year - 2014
Publication title -
philosophy and phenomenological research
Language(s) - English
Resource type - Journals
SCImago Journal Rank - 1.7
H-Index - 39
eISSN - 1933-1592
pISSN - 0031-8205
DOI - 10.1111/j.1933-1592.2012.00646.x
Subject(s) - philosophy , epistemology
Normative branches of philosophy take special interest in claims expressed by sentences of the form ‘S ought to !’, where S is some agent and !-ing is some action (broadly conceived). We’ll call sentences satisfying this description agential. These claims raise many important philosophical issues, such as: Which ones are true? What makes them true? How can we know if they are true? What follows from them? Some philosophers have hoped that light would be cast on these issues if we could get clearer on the exact meaning of this word ‘ought’. Once we start looking to language for philosophical clues we should notice that the word ‘ought’ is also employed in different kinds of sentence. It appears in normative sentences with different grammatical forms, like ‘It ought to be that Charlie was born a girl’, and ‘There ought to be less suffering in the world’. For convenience we’ll call sentences like these nonagential. (It also has a non-normative epistemic use meaning approximately what is probable, as in ‘The sky ought to get dark soon’.) In these other sentences, ‘ought’ appears to represent a propositional operator, O(p).

This content is not available in your region!

Continue researching here.

Having issues? You can contact us here